Quotient
The relation used in a quotient type must be symmetric and transitive, also known as a partial equivalence relation:
PER : intersect (i : level) . forall (A : U i) . (A -> A -> U i) -> U i
= fn A R .
(forall (x y : A) . R x y -> R y x) & (forall (x y z : A) . R x y -> R y z -> R x z)
quotient_formation : forall (i : level) (A : U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) .
PER A R -> (quotient (x y : A) . R x y) : U i
The quotient type does not have an introduction form, which sometimes
causes difficulties for the type checker. An alternative presentation
of quotient types, called quotient1
, uses an introduction form:
quotient1 : intersect (i : level) . forall (A : U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) . PER A R -> U i
= fn A R Hper . quotient (x y : A) . R x y
qintro1 : intersect (i : level) .
forall (A : U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) (Hper : PER A R) (x : A) .
R x x -> quotient1 A R Hper
= fn A R Hper x Hx . x
Suppose x
belongs to a quotient. When x
is destructed to obtain
x'
, x'
has a different type than x
(i.e., the underlying
type). This can complicate typechecking. However, when x
belongs
to quotient1 A R Hper
, destructing x
creates
qintro1 A R Hper x' hx
which can easily be determined still to have
the same type.
Nevertheless, quotient (x y : A) . R x y
is interchangeable with
quotient1 A R Hper
, and x
is interchangeable with
qintro1 A R Hper x hx
, simply by using fold and unfold.
A common pattern for quotient types is to use a constraining predicate
(Q
below), as well as a relation between representatives. We
recapitulate the tools for this common pattern.
PER2 : intersect (i : level) . forall (A : U i) . (A -> U i) -> (A -> A -> U i) -> U i
= fn A Q R .
(forall (x : A) . Q x -> R x x)
& (forall (x y : A) . Q x -> Q y -> R x y -> R y x)
& (forall (x y z : A) . Q x -> Q y -> Q z -> R x y -> R y z -> R x z)
quotient2_formation : forall (i : level) (A : U i) (Q : A -> U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) .
PER2 A Q R -> (quotient (x y : A) . Q x & Q y & R x y) : U i
quotient2 : intersect (i : level) .
forall (A : U i) (Q : A -> U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) . PER2 A Q R -> U i
= fn A Q R Hper . quotient (x y : A) . Q x & Q y & R x y
qintro2 : intersect (i : level) .
forall (A : U i) (Q : A -> U i) (R : A -> A -> U i) (Hper : PER2 A Q R) (x : A) .
Q x -> quotient2 A Q R Hper
= fn A Q R Hper x Hx . x
When using the extensionality
tactic to prove
M = N : quotient2 A Q R H
, it is necessary to prove Q M
and
Q N
. However, if we already know that M
and N
belong to
quotient2 A Q R H
, those obligations are redundant. The
quotient2_equality
lemma provides an easier way to prove equality in
such cases.
quotient2_equality : forall
(i : level)
(A : U i)
(Q : A -> U i)
(R : A -> A -> U i)
(Hper : PER2 A Q R)
(x y : quotient2 A Q R Hper) .
{ R x y } -> x = y : quotient2 A Q R Hper
(The squash in the type is necessary. Since R
works on the
underlying type, rather than on the quotient, it is necessary to draw
representatives from x
’s and y
’s equivalence classes. But then we
have R x y <-> R x' y'
but not (in general) R x y = R x' y'
when
x
and x'
(and y
and y'
) are merely related. However
{ R x y }
and { R x' y' }
are equal types, since squash contracts
logical equivalence to type equality.)